Page images
PDF
EPUB

Our philosophical definition of Beauty has thus taken final shape. The beautiful object possesses those qualities which bring the personality into a state of unity and self-completeness. Lightly to cast aside such a definition as abstract, vague, empty, is no less short sighted than to treat the idea of the Absolute Will, of the Transcendental Reason, of the Eternal Love, as mere intellectual factors in the æsthetic experience. It should not be criticised as giving "no objective account of the nature and origin of Beauty." The nature of Beauty is indicated in the definition; the origin of Beauty may be studied in its historical development; its reason for being is simply the desire of the human heart for the perfect moment.

Beauty is to bring unity and self-completeness | into the personality. By what means? What causes can bring about this effect? When we enter the realm of causes and effects, however, we have already left the ground of philosophy, and it is fitting that the concepts which we have to use should be adapted to the empirical point of view. The personality, as dealt with in psychology, is but the pyschophysical organism; and we need to know only how to translate unity and self-completeness into psychological terms.

The psychophysical organism is in a state of unity either when it is in a state of virtual congealment or emptiness, as in a trance or ecstasy; or when it is in a state of repose, without tendency to change.

Secondly, the organism is self-complete when it is at the highest possible point of tone, of functional efficiency, of enhanced life. Then a combination of favorable stimulation and repose would characterize the æsthetic feeling.

But it may be said that stimulation and repose are contradictory concepts, and we must indeed admit that the absolute repose of the hypnotic trance is not æsthetic, because empty of stimulus. The only æsthetic repose is that in which stimulation resulting in impulse to movement or action is checked or compensated for by its antagonistic impulse; inhibition of action, or action returning upon itself, combined with heightening of tone. But this is tension, equilibrium, or balance of forces, which is thus seen to be a general condition of all æsthetic experience. The concept is familiar in pictorial composition and to some extent also in music and poetry, but here first appears as grounded in the very demand for the union of repose with activity.

Moreover, this requirement, which we have derived from the logical concepts of unity and totality, as translated into psychological terms, receives confirmation from the nature of organic life. It was the perfect moment that we sought, and we found it in the immediate experience of unity and selfcompleteness; and unity for a living being can only be equilibrium. Now it appears that an authoritative definition of the general nature of an organism makes it "so built, whether on mechanical

principles or not, that every deviation from the equilibrium point sets up a tendency to return to it." 1 Equilibrium, in greater or less excursions from the centre, is thus the ultimate nature of organic life. The perfect equilibrium, that is, equilibrium with heightened tone, will then give the perfect moment.

The further steps of æsthetics are then toward analysis of the psychological effect of all the elements which enter into a work of art, with reference to their effect in producing stimulation or repose. What colors, forms, tones, emotions, ideas, favorably stimulate? What combinations of these bring to repose? All the modern studies in socalled physiological æsthetics, into the emotional and other especially motor-effects of color, tone-sensation, melodic sequence, simple forms, etc., find here their proper place.

A further important question, as to the fitting psychological designation of the æsthetic state, is now suggested. Some authorities speak of the æsthetic attitude or activity, describing it as "sympathetic imitation" or "absorption;" others of the æsthetic pleasure. But, according to our definition of the æsthetic experience as a combination of favorable stimulation with repose, this state, as involving "a distinctive feeling-tone and a characteristic trend of activity aroused by a certain situation," 2 can be no other than an emotion. This view is

1 L. T. Hobhouse, Mind in Evolution.

2 Baldwin's Dict. of Phil. and Psychol. Art. "Emotion."

confirmed by introspection; we speak of æsthetic activity and æsthetic pleasure, but we are conscious of a complete arrest, and sometimes of a very distinct divergence from pure pleasure. The experience is unique, it seems to defy description, to be intense, vivid, and yet—like itself alone. Any attempt to disengage special, already known emotions, even at the play or in hearing music, is often in vain, in just those moments when our excitement is most intense. But the hypothesis of a unique emotion, parallel to those of joy, fear, etc., and with a psychological basis as outlined, would account for these facts. The positive toning of the experience -what we call æsthetic pleasure-is due not only to the favorable stimulation, but also to the fact that the very antagonism of impulses which constitutes repose heightens tone while it inhibits action. Thus the conditions of both factors of æsthetic emotion tend to induce pleasure.

It is, then, clear that no specific æsthetic pleasure need be sought. The very phrase, indeed, is a misnomer, since all pleasure is qualitatively the same, and differentiated only by the specific activities which it accompanies. It is also to be noted that those writers on æsthetics who have dwelt most on æsthetic pleasure have come in conclusion only to specific activities, like the "imitation" of Groos, for instance. In the light of the just-won definition of æsthetic emotion, it is interesting to examine some of the well-known modern æsthetic theories.

Lipps defines the æsthetic experience as a "thrill of sympathetic feeling," Groos as "sympathetic imitation," evidently assuming that pleasure accompanies this. But there are many feelings of sympathy, and joyful ones, which do not belong to the æsthetic realm. In the same way, not all "imitation" is accompanied by pleasure, and not all of that falls within the generally accepted æsthetic field. If these definitions were accepted as they stand, all our rejoicings with friends, all our inspiration from a healthy, magnetic presence must be included in it. It is clear that further limitation is necessary; but if to this sympathetic imitation, this living through in sympathy, we add the demand for repose, the necessary limitation is made. Physical exercise in general, or the instinctive imitation of energetic, or easy (in general favorable) movements, is pleasurable, indeed, but the experience is not æsthetic, as is quite clear, indeed, to common sense, and it is not æsthetic because it is the contradiction of repose. A particular case of the transformation of pleasurable physical exercise into an æsthetic activity is seen in the experience of symmetrical or balanced form; any moderate, smooth exercise of the eye is pleasurable, but this alone induces a state of the whole organism combining repose with stimulation.

[ocr errors]
[ocr errors]

The theories of Külpe and Santayana, while they definitely mark out the ground, seem to me in need of addition. "Absorption in the object in

« ՆախորդըՇարունակել »