Page images
PDF
EPUB
[ocr errors]

largely insisted upon it, has established it with all the strength of his capacious understanding, and ennobled it with all the magnificence of his divine imagination. He has one passage so full and clear on this head, that I am persuaded the reader will be pleased to see it here, though somewhat long. Addressing himself to such as are not satisfied concerning divine Providence: The Being who presides over the whole," says he, has disposed and complicated all things for the happiness and virtue of the whole, every part of which, according to the extent of its influence, does and suffers what is fit and proper. One of these parts is yours, O unhappy man, which though in itself most inconsiderable and minute, yet being connected with the universe, ever seeks to co-operate with that Supreme order. You in the mean time are ignorant of the very end for which all particular natures are brought into existence, that the all-comprehending nature of the whole may be perfect and happy; existing, as it does, not for your sake, but the cause and reason of your existence, which, as in the symmetry of every artificial work, must of necessity concur with the general design of the artist, and be subservient to the whole, of which it is a part. Your complaint, therefore, is ignorant and groundless; since, according to the various energy of creation and the common laws of nature, there is a constant provision of that which is best at the same time for you and for the whole. For the governing Intelligence, clearly beholding all the actions of animated and self-moving creatures, and that mixture of good and evil which diversifies them, considered first of all by what dis position of things, and by what situation of each individual in the general system, vice might be depressed and subdued, and virtue made secure of victory and happiness with the greatest facility and in the highest degree possible. In this ma ner he ordered, through the entire circle of being, the internal constitution of every mind, where should be its station in the_universal fabric, and through what variety of circumstances it should proceed in the whole tenor of its existence." He goes on n his sublime manner to assert a future state of retribution, "as well for those who, by the exercise of good dispositions being harmonized and assimilated into the divine virtue, are consequently removed to a place of unblemished sanctity and happiness, as of those who by the most flagitious arts have risen from contemptible beginnings to the greatest affluence and power, and whom you therefore look upon as unanswerable instances of negligence in the gods, because you are ignorant of the purposes to which they are subservient, and in what manner they contribute to that supreme intention of good to the whole."- Plato de Leg. x. 16.

This theory has been delivered of late, especially abroad, in a manner which subverts the freedom of human actions; whereas Plato appears very careful to preserve it, and has been in that respect imitated by the best of his followers.

[ocr errors]

Ver. 321.

one might rise,

One order, &c.] See the Meditations of Antoni-
Characteristics, passim.

nus and the
Ver. 355. The best and fairest, &c.] This opinion is so old,
that Timæus Locrus calls the Supreme Being Sprovayds tov
BEATiovos, the artificer of that which is best; and represents
him as resolving in the beginning to produce the most excel-
lent work, and as copying the world most exactly from his own
intelligible and essential idea; "so that it yet remains, as it
was at first, perfect in beauty, and will never stand in need
of any correction or improvement." There can be no room
for a caution here, to understand the expressions, not of any
particular circumstances of human life separately considered,
but of the sun or universal system of life and being. See also
the vision at the end of the Theodicée of Leibnitz.

Ver. 350. As flame ascends, &c.] This opinion, though not held by Plato nor any of the ancients, is yet a very natural consequence of his principles. But the disisition is too colaplex and extensive to be entered upon here.

Ver. 755. Philip.] The Macedonian.

VER. 18.

NOTES ON BOOK III.

where the powers

of fancy, &c.] The influence of the imagination on the conduct of life is one of the most important points in moral philosophy. It were easy, by an induction of facts, to prove that the imagination directs almost all the passions, and mixes with almost every circumstance of action or pleasure. Let any man, even of the coldest head and soberest industry, analyse the idea of what he calls his interest; he will find that it consists chiefly of certain degrees of decency, beauty, and order, variously combined into one system, the idol which he seeks to enjoy by labour, hazard, and self-denial. It is on this account of the last consequence to regulate these images by the standard of nature and the general good; otherwise the imagination, by heightening some objects beyond their real excellence and beauty, or by representing others in odious or terrible shape than they deserve, may of course engage us in pursuits utterly inconsistent with the moral order of things.

more

If it be objected that this account of things supposes the passions to be merely accidental, whereas there appears in

some a natural and hereditary disposition to certain passions prior to all circumstances of education or fortune; it may be answered, that though no man is born ambitious or a miser, yet he may inherit from his parents a peculiar temper or complexion of mind, which shall render his imagination more liable to be struck with some particular objects, consequently dispose him to form opinions of good and ill, and entertain passions of a particular turn. Some men, for instance, by the original frame of their minds, are more delighted with the vast and magnificent, others on the contrary with the elegant and gentle aspects of nature. And it is very remarkable, that the disposition of the moral powers is always similar to this of the imagination; that those who are most inclined to admire prodigious and sublime objects in the physical world are also most inclined to applaud examples of fortitude and heroic virtue in the moral. While those who are charmed rather with the delicacy and sweetness of colours, and forms, and sounds, never fail in like manner to yield the preference to the softer scenes of virtue and the sympathies of a domestic life. And this is sufficient to account for the objection.

[ocr errors]

Among the ancient philosophers, though we have several hints concerning this influence of the imagination upon morals among the remains of the Socratic school, yet the Stoics were the first who paid it a due attention. Zeno, their founder, thought it impossible to preserve any tolerable regularity in life, without frequently inspecting those pictures or appearances of things, which the imagination offers to the mind (Diog. Laert. vi). The meditations of M. Aurelius, and the discourses of Epictetus, are full of the same sentiment; insomuch that the latter makes the Χρήσις οἷα δεῖ, φαντασιών, or right management of the fancies, the only thing for which we are accountable to Providence, and without which a man is no other than stupid Gr frantic. Arrian. 1. i. c. 12, and 1. ii. c. 22. See also the Caracteristics, vol. i. from p. 313 to 321, where this stoical S doctrine is einbellished with all the elegance and graces of

Plaz to.

Notwith

Ver. 75. how Folly's awkward arts, &c.] staiding the general influence of ridicule on private and civil life as well as on learning and the sciences, it has been almost Constantly neglected or misrepresented, by divines especially. The manner of treating these subjects in the science of human nature should be precisely the same as in natural philosophy; from particular facts to investigate the stated order in which they appear, and then apply the general law, thus discovered, to the explication of other appearances and the improvement of

useful arts.

Ver. 84. Behold the foremost band, &c.] The first and most eneral source of ridicule in the characters of men is vanity, or self-pplause for some desirable quality or possession which evidently does not belong to those who assume it.

Ver. 121. Then comes the second order, &c. Ridicule from the same vanity, where, though the possession be real, yet no merit can arise from it, because of some particular circumstances, which, though obvious to the spectator, are yet overlooked by the ridiculous character.

Ver. 152. Another tribe succeeds, &c.] Ridicule from a notion of excellence in particular objects disproportioned to their intrinsic value, and inconsistent with the order of nature.

Ver. 191. But now, ye gay, &c.] Ridicule from a notion of excellence, when the object is absolutely odious or contemptible. This is the highest degree of the ridiculous; as in the affectation of diseases or vices.

Ver. 207. Thus far triumphant, &c.] Ridicule from false shame or groundless fear.

Ver. 228. Last of the, &c.] Ridicule from the ignorance of such things as our circumstances require us to know.

Ver. 248. Suffice it to have said, &c.] By comparing these general sources of ridicule with each other, and examining the ridiculous in other objects, we may obtain a general definition of it, equally applicable to every species. The most important circumstance of this definition is laid down in the lines referred to; but others more minute we shall subjoin here. Aristotle's account of the matter seems both imperfect and false; rò yàp γελοῖόν, says he, έστιν ἁμάρτημά τι καὶ αίσχος, ἀνώδυνον καὶ οὐ p0aprikov: "the ridiculous is some certain fault or turpitude without pain, and not destructive to its subject" (Poet. c. 5). For allowing it to be true, as it is not, that the ridiculous is never accompanied with pain, yet we might produce many instances of such a fault or turpitude which cannot with any tolerable propriety be called ridiculous. So that the definition does not distinguish the thing designed. Nay, farther: even when we perceive the turpitude tending to the destruction of its subject, we may still be sensible of a ridiculous appearance, till the ruin become imminent, and the keener sensations of pity or terror banish the ludicrous apprehension from our minds. For the sensation of ridicule is not a bare perception of the agreement or disagreement of ideas; but a passion or emotion of the mind consequential to that perception. So that the mind may perceive the agreement or disagreement, and yet not feel the ridiculous, because it is engrossed by a more violent emotion. Thus it happens that some men think those objects ridiculous to which others cannot endure to apply the name, because in them they excite a much intenser and more important feeling, And this difference, among other causes, has brought a good deal of confusion into this question.

That which makes objects ridiculous is some ground of admiration or esteem connected with other more general circumstances comparatively worthless or deformed; or it is some circumstance of turpitude or deformity connected with what is in general excellent or beautiful: the inconsistent properties

existing either in the objects themselves, or in the apprehension of the person to whom they relate; belonging always to the same order or class of being; implying sentiment or design; and exciting no acute or vehement emotion of the heart. The appearTo prove the several parts of this definition: ance of excellence or beauty connected with a general condition comparatively sordid or deformed, is ridiculous; for instance, pompous pretensions of wisdom joined with ignorance or folly in the Socrates of Aristophanes, and the ostentations of military glory with cowardice and stupidity in the Thraso of

Terence.

The appearance of deformity or turpitude in conjunction with what is in general excellent or venerable, is also ridiculous; for instance, the personal weaknesses of a magistrate appearing in the solemn and public functions of his station.

relate.

The incongruous properties may either exist in the objects themselves, or in apprehension of the person to whom they In the last-mentioned instance, they both exist in the objects; in the instances from Aristophanes and Terence, one of them is objective and real, the other only founded in the apprehension of the ridiculous character.

The inconsistent properties must belong to the same order or class of being. A coxcomb in fine clothes, bedaubed by accident in foul weather, is a ridiculous object; because his general apprehension of excellence and esteem is referred to the splendour and expense of his dress. A man of sense and merit, in the same circumstances, is not counted ridiculous; because the general ground of excellence and esteem in him is, both in fact and in his own apprehension, of a very different species.

A

Every ridiculous object implies sentiment or design. column placed by an architect without a capital or base is I ughed at: the same column in a ruin causes a very different

sensation.

And, lastly, the occurrence must excite no acute or vehement emotion of the heart, such as terror, pity, or indignation; for in that case, as was observed above, the mind is not at leisure to contemplate the ridiculous.

Whether any appearance not ridiculous be involved in this description, and whether it comprehend every species and form of the ridiculous, must be determined by repeated applications of it to particular instances.

Ver. 259. Ask we for what fair end, &c.] Since it is beyond all contradiction evident that we have a natural sense or feeling of the ridiculous, and since so good a reason may be assigned to justify the Supreme Being for bestowing it, one cannot, without astonishment, reflect on the conduct of those men who imagine it is for the service of true religion to vilify and blacken it wit out distinction, and endeavour to persuade us that it is never applied but in a bad cause. Ridicule is not concerned

« ՆախորդըՇարունակել »